May 24, 2025

laborday 2016

Building the Future, Success Together

The Ethics of a ‘Passive’ Investment

The Ethics of a ‘Passive’ Investment

The nexus between surplus, ethics, and endeavor

Whatever you make of a philosophical argument that assumes a world in which land is not only synonymous with wealth but ripe for the taking, Locke’s theory of property illustrates the nexus between surplus, ethics, and endeavor. By virtue of some undertaking, I gain the benefit of the endeavor. The surplus is fairly mine, and no one can simply seize it without committing an injustice.

Seen in this light, the accumulation of private property becomes an extended exercise in just desserts. I get property and the benefits it confers not because I take it by force (the Genghis Khan approach to wealth accumulation), nor because of divine right (the feudal account), but because I have earned it.

Still, these benefits do not come cheaply. “There are no gains without pains,” Father Abraham warns in “The Way to Wealth,” perhaps the most famous entry in Poor Richard’s Almanack, the gallimaufry of poems, essays, proverbial wisdom, weather forecasts, mathematical exercises, and stargazing schedules that Benjamin Franklin published annually from 1732 to 1758.

Franklin is a paragon of sorts for the Lockean notion of property accumulation, a vision encapsulated by another chestnut from Father Abraham: “Help hands, for I have no lands.” A runaway printer’s apprentice, Franklin famously made his way to Philadelphia and eventually found his fortune by dint of hard work, careful study, and, by his own account as well as those of his admirers, the cultivation of what is sometimes called the bourgeois virtues.

As one such admirer, Franklin’s occasional pen pal Adam Smith, wrote of the commercial promise of such virtues: “In all the middling and inferior professions, real and solid professional abilities, joined to prudent, just, firm, and temperate conduct, can very seldom fail of success.” For Smith as for Franklin, it wasn’t enough to work hard. If one wanted to accumulate property and underwrite a long-term plan for success, hard work and careful study, the prerequisites of any “professional abilities,” had to be complemented by a suite of virtues that supported personal responsibility and public spiritedness. “The success of such people, too, almost always depends upon the favour and good opinion of their neighbours and equals,” Smith continued, “and without a tolerably regular conduct these can very seldom be obtained.”

Property, on this account, was something owned, operated, and maintained within the scrupulous expectations of a well-defined community. Having a horse to plow your land was all well and good, but you were the one who had to follow the plow in planting season and run all over the neighborhood if the horse escaped the barn.

This conception of private property, the significance of which went well beyond revenue streams and financial security, both assumed and encouraged a broader vision of a well-ordered society. The philosopher David Hume, another of Franklin’s correspondents, wrote in one of his most famous essays that broadly distributing private property and the rights and responsibilities that attend it creates social conditions that are conducive to what today we would call a liberal democratic order. “Where luxury nourishes commerce and industry,” Hume declared, “the peasants, by a proper cultivation of the land, become rich and independent; while the tradesmen and merchants acquire a share of the property, and draw authority and consideration to that middling rank of men, who are the best and firmest basis of public liberty.”

Like his friends Smith and Franklin, Hume believed the very practice of accumulating and maintaining private property was not only a sustained exercise in prudence and careful management, but also the foundation for a stable, responsible society and an education in citizenship.

Absentee ownership

Notably, Hume, Smith, and Franklin exchanged their trans-Atlantic letters more than 50 years before the full flowering of the Industrial Revolution. Even then, the nexus of surplus, ethics, and endeavor so central to the Lockean vision of private property was already imperiled by the rise of wage labor. Smith’s celebrated account of how a pin is made in the opening pages of The Wealth of Nations—“One man draws out the wire, another straights it, a third cuts it”—shows that he well understood that the division of labor (what he termed “the greatest improvement in the productive powers of labour”) would fracture this nexus. True, the workers who helped make a pin would certainly collect a wage, but they could work their entire lives in the factory without ever even owning the stools they sat on.

Still, if wage labor did not sit neatly in the worldview implied by Locke’s theory of property, it hardly rendered that theory null and void. “The prudent, penniless beginner in the world, labors for wages awhile, saves a surplus with which to buy tools or land, for himself,” Abraham Lincoln declared in 1859, “then labors on his own account another while, and at length hires another new beginner to help him.” A rising star of the newly incorporated Republican Party, which was then only five years old, Lincoln captured a kind of hopeful ambivalence about how wage labor might shape society. Yes, insofar as one worked principally with another’s property, the experience did not lend itself to the kind of moral education figures such as Hume envisioned, but so long as it eventually enabled one to become a property owner, wage labor was something like a way station between abject servitude and a substantial sense of self-reliance.

link

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Copyright © All rights reserved. | Newsphere by AF themes.